âIn the first of our dialogues about the mind, Riccardo Manzotti and I established that by âconsciousnessâ we mean the feeling that accompanies our being alive, the fact that we experience the world rather than simply interacting with it mechanically.â
âWe also touched on the problem that traditional science cannot explain this fact and does not include it in its account of reality.â
âThat said, there is a dominant understanding of where consciousness happens: in the brain. This âinternalist,â or inside-the-head, approach shares Galileoâs view that color, smell, and sound do not exist in the outside world but only in the brain.â
âTim Parks: Riccardo, when the internalists talk about conscious experience, they often use the word âqualia,â meaning an elementary sensation, a feeling of something, and one of their favorite examples of this is our seeing color, our experience of color. So how does it come about that we see color?â
âRiccardo Manzotti: Before answering letâs pay some attention to the language weâre using, since it may determine the way we think about the whole thing. Most people say they see a color or a colored object, a yellow banana, say. So we have subject and object; a person sees a yellow banana. Scientists and philosophers speak of our having an experience, feeling, or qualia. So now we have three things, a subject, an object (the banana maybe), and a feeling, in our heads. I fear both manners of speaking are potentially misleading.â
âthe subject/object divide, not to mention the addition of a feeling or âpercept,â is particularly pertinent when we talk about color.â
âscience tells us thereâs no color in the world. It occurs only in our brains. But, as we discussed in our first conversation, when scientists look inside the brain to see whatâs going on, they find only billions of neurons exchanging electrical impulses and releasing chemical substances. They find what they call correlates of consciousness, not consciousness itself; or in this case, they find correlates of color, but not color itself. There is no yellow banana in the head, just the grey stuff.â
âThe unsuspecting layman will assure you that objects simply have colors as attributesâisnât our banana, for example, very yellow exactly the same way itâs six inches long? Well, unfortunately not, because it could easily be shown that bananas are only yellow under a certain light. Change the light and the banana might look green. But it will always be six inches long.â
âFrom the nineteenth century on scientists have been looking for colors inside the nervous system. First they worked on the hypothesis that colors were qualities that the retina or the optic nerve introduced into the signals that they then sent to areas further along in the brain. However, nothing satisfactory was ever found, nor is it clear what they imagined they might find.â
âthe current textbook view goes like this. The world is a place where objects reflect light, sunlight being the dominant source and as it were default setting as far as the kind of light is concerned. However, each object reflects only a subset of that light. Rays from this subset enter our retina and stimulate a honeycomb of cells, known as cones, because of their conical shape, whose function is to react differently to different portions of the visible spectrum (we remember of course that only a small part of the vast electromagnetic spectrum is visible). Most humansâanimals are rather different of courseâpossess three kinds of cones, referred to as S, M, and L cones, depending on whether they react more vigorously to short, medium or long-range light wavelengths. The âoutputâ of these cells is first merged together in the retina then sent via the optical nerve to various cortical areasâincluding the famous V4. And thatâs as much as we know.â
âthis is a theory of color that does not need the notion of colors. I suppose the reason is that however carefully you follow neural signals from the retina along the optic nerve and across the brain you donât actually come across anything like a color, or anything that explains color perception. You could almost say that the notion of color is useless to color science, unlessâŚâ
âParks: Unless?â
âManzotti: Unless we bring consciousness back in the picture. Colors are something we experience, individually and collectively. But without our experience of color, science would have no reason to suspect its existence.â
âRather than insisting that the same pixels should always appear as the same color and talking about an appearance/reality gap what science should be doing is accepting the reality of conscious experience and questioning its own obviously imperfect understanding of what constitutes color.â
âParks: I recall now how the neuroscientist Christof Koch claims that our experience of color is âa con job.â David Eagleman talks about vision being the result of âfancy editing tricks.â The philosopher Eric Schwitzgebel accuses us of being âignorant and prone to errorâ about everything we see. A moral nuance is smuggled into the debate, as if there were something shabby and lazy in the way we see the world. It feels like weâre being blamed, or condescended to, for not perceiving things as science thinks we ought to.â
âManzotti: Exactly. Kitaokaâs illusionâand there are many others like itâbecomes a flash point where the assertions of science in the Galileo tradition clash with the validity of our conscious perception.â
âwhat we need to do is to get beyond the idea that consciousness is a ârepresentationâ of the world at all. Maybe it is simply reality. Maybe, as I hinted at the beginning, we have to do away with that subject/object distinction which lies behind this whole discussion.â
âThis is the second in a series by Riccardo Manzotti and Tim Parks on consciousness.â
Navigation
Backlinks
There are no backlinks to this post.