âGraham Harmanâs philosophy of science promulgates an absolute difference between the ârealâ object as posited in his philosophy and the âsensualâ object, i.e. both the theoretical object of science and the ideological object of common sense and of the humanities.â
âDespite apparent connivences between Harman and Bruno Latour, everything separates them on the issue of realism in relation to the sciences. Latour distinguishes in his Gifford Lecures between an illusory monist, a-historical âScience Oneâ claiming direct access to the world and a really existing âScience Twoâ that is realist precisely because it is pluralist, historical, animated, mediated, and controversy-rich.â
âHarman judges science in terms of philosophical criteria of another age (Science One) and finds it lacking in reality. He is then obliged to posit a shadowy âwithdrawnâ realm of real objects to explain the discrepancies between his naive abstract model and the reality of the sciences.â
âTHE THIRD TABLE is the record of Haman noticing the discrepancies, but the solution he proposes is a dead-end, a regressive rearguard action masquerading as a decisive progress with respect to a supposedly idealist (or âcorrelationistâ) post-structuralism.â
âFoucauldian power is not equivalent to subjectivity, nor is it even human-centered. The same applies tos Heideggerâs language or Deleuze and Guattariâs desire. There is no primacy of human access or of âcorrelationâ in these systems.â
âOn the contrary, these conceptual assemblages were elaborated precisely to get away from what has come to be called the correlationist trap. They are part of these thinkersâ project of reconceptualisation of the supposedly familiar phenomena of everyday life.â
âHarmanâs concept of âwithdrawalâ, on the other hand, is not an innovative revisioning of such familiar phenomena, but represents an incredible simplification of the world that renders it computable while dispensing us of the need to individuate it and individuate ourselves with it.â
âThere can be no withdrawal without abundance (in Feyerabendâs sense in his CONQUEST OF ABUNDANCE), but abundance can and does exist without withdrawal.â
ââWithdrawalâ is tied to a calulative or computational understanding of Being. The sensual object, demoted to the status of âutter shamâ, is de-valorised ontologically in favour of the real object that is purely intelligible. Abstractions are given primacy over what makes a concrete difference in our lives.â
âThe computational understanding of Being is the understanding that originates with Descartes and renders possible the various specific computational disciplines that exist today.â
âIt is the hegemony of the âcountâ. This is what de-valorises the sensual qualities to mere secondary status . Harmanâs real objects are not sensible but only intelligible in the sense that they can only be objects of our intellection.â
âThey are transcendent abstractions (unknowable and untouchable, according to Harman). Both for the Homeric understanding (i.e. prior to Platoâs invention of metaphysics with its bifurcation of Being into real and apparent) and for our post-Nietzschean world things do not withdraw, rather they assemble and abound.â
âDespite its promises, Harmanâs OOO does not bring us closer to the richness and complexity of the real world but in fact replaces the multiplicitous and variegated world with a set of bloodless and lifeless abstractions â his unknowable and untouchable, âghostlyâ, objects.â
âHarmanâs exposition of his system may begin with a preliminary gesture of recognising the multiplicity and abundance of the world, but he rapidly reduces these concretely given multiple elements to overarching âemergentâ unities that exclude other approaches to and understandings of the world (cf. THE THIRD TABLE) â OOOâs objects are the âonly realâ objects.â
âHarman does not really begin from ânaivetĂ©â. He produces and persuasively imposes a highly technical concept of object such that it replaces the familiar objects of the everyday world, and the less familiar objects of science with something âdeeperâ and âinaccessibleâ.â
âHe then proceeds to equivocate with the familiar connotations and associations of âobjectâ to give the impression that he is a concrete thinker, when his philosophy takes us to new heights of abstraction: the real is the unknowable, ineffable, untouchable object that withdraws.â
âAccording to Harmanâs THE THIRD TABLE (page 12):
The world is filled primarily not with electrons or human praxis, but with ghostly objects withdrawing from all human and inhuman access.â
âYet Harmanâs OOO has legislated that its object is the only real object. In THE THIRD TABLE Harman calls his table, as compared to the table of everyday life and the scientistâs table, âthe only real oneâ (10), and âthe only real tableâ (11). As for the everyday table and the scientific table: âboth are equally unrealâ, both are âutter shamsâ (6). âWhatever we capture, whatever we sit at or destroy is not the real tableâ (12). And he accuses others of âreductionismâ! Harman constantly conflates ontological and epistemological theses while proudly claiming the contrary. To say that the real object is unknowable (âthe real is something that cannot be knownâ, 12) is an epistemological thesis. As is the claim that the object we know, the everyday or the scientific object, is unreal.â
âHarman needs his âsensualâ objects, despite being obliged to declare them unreal (âutter shamsâ) because he has an impoverished notion of reality, and also of scientific research. The bifurcation operated by the notion of âwithdrawalâ is too absolute (there are no degrees of withdrawal) and thus splits the world a priori into two (real/sensual) realms. Harmanâs system is too globalising with its dualisms to be able to deal with the fine-grained distinctions that come up in our experience.â
Navigation
Backlinks
There are no backlinks to this post.