âAfter decades of careful and productive philosophical work, it may be that the seams of descriptive metaphysics have been all but mined out. Fortunately, as Leemon B. McHenry beautifully illustrates, after more than a half-century of slumber the speculative impulse has been reawakened.â
âMcHenry is attempting, fallibly if not immodestly, nothing less than âa general theory of the worldâ (vii). Building on the work of Bertrand Russell, W. V. O. Quine, and, most especially, Alfred North Whitehead, the authorâs aim is to frame an event ontology that is fully consistent with contemporary physics, especially physicistsâ attempts to create a unified theory or so-called Theory of Everything (TOE). For those readers who are eager to place this pigeon in its proper hole, McHenry characterizes his project as revisionary, naturalistic, and realistic.â
âstarting with the work of three Cambridge philosophers, Whitehead, Russell, and C. D. Broad. McHenry notes that early in the century all three philosophers developed event ontologies in conversation with the emerging relativity theory (2).â
âMcHenry contends, it is the attempt to construct a metaphysics that is adequate to the discoveries of electromagnetism, relativity theory, and, later, quantum mechanics, that makes a compelling case for the rejection of a substance ontology in favor of an event ontology.â
âAs he colorfully puts it, the âmetaphysical megalomania in the likes of Descartes, Spinoza, Hegel and Bradley is thereby cured by a naturalised approach inspired by the American pragmatists, Pierce, James and Dewey. The quest for certainty is abandoned both in philosophy and scienceâ (5). Pierce and Whitehead are particularly good examples of this new approach to speculative philosophy, according to which a metaphysical theory is seen as a âworking hypothesisâ that should continually be tested for its applicability and adequacy to concrete experience.â
âConceived in this manner, metaphysics as âfirst philosophyâ must surrender its traditional claim to a truth beyond the empirical realm of scientific investigation. A plea for open systems replaces the alleged finality of absolute principles or the sacrosanct status of the common-sense conceptual scheme (8).â
âOn this model, both physics and metaphysics do not attempt to create closed, necessary, apodictic systems of truths immune to revision, but they conduct fallible, open-ended pursuit of ever-more-adequate accounts of reality.â
âMcHenry contends that it is this embrace of the traditional, Aristotelian conception of substance that brings Strawson to subordinate events and processes to substantial things. Events are merely activities of substances (15). In contrast, McHenryâs goal is to follow and defend Whitehead, Russell, and Quineâs âbroad viewâ of events, according to whichâ
âevents are the only concrete or basic particulars and substance is eliminated as an unnecessary substratum. The concern of the anti-event metaphysicians gets reversed; instead of eliminating events to keep our ontology tidy, we eliminate substances (16).â
âFurthermore, McHenry points out, there is reason to wonder whether the subject-predicate form of âourâ ordinary language isnât already biasing us toward a substance ontology. Indeed, he approvingly cites Tsu-Lin Meiâs argument that philosophers like Strawson may be guilty of a form of âlinguistic imperialismâ becauseâ
âhe takes English as the paradigm for all languages. Since Chinese does not admit a distinction between subject and predicate, the so-called conceptual scheme of ordinary language describes at most âa fact peculiar to Indo-European languages and has no further philosophical significanceâ (1961: 153) (25).â
âThe implication is that, according to McHenryâs revisionary event ontology, the relationship of events and objects is reversed. âEvents are energetic activities interrelated in such a way as to form a network or field of relations; objects such as electrons, atoms, molecules and the like are disturbances or vibrations in the field. They are all patterns discernible in event-sequencesâ (29).â
âChapter four is the heart of the project. It is here that McHenry carefully considers the affinities and contrasts in the event theories advanced by Whitehead, Russell, and Quine respectively. Whiteheadâs early event ontology and later process ontology are the backbone of McHenryâs project, as implied by the subtitle of the work.â
âAdmirably avoiding the scholastic habits of some Whitehead scholars, the author explains Whiteheadâs complex metaphysics in clear language with a minimum of technical jargon. Realizing the significance of Maxwellâs work, which was the subject of his doctoral thesis, and in reaction Einsteinâs theories of relativity, Whitehead proposed an event ontology according to whichâ
âEverything in the universe from medium-size dry goods to planets and galaxies, is interpreted as patterns of properties that are repeated in event sequences. âThingsâ, as we ordinarily understand them, are postulated by Whitehead to be relatively monotonous patterns in events (51).â
âThe advantage of Whiteheadâs approach is that it provides an ontology that can coherently explain and unify the macroscopic world that we inhabit with the microscopic world of the physicist.â
âMcHenry turns next to Russell and his âneutral monismâ or the view that âthe ultimate stuff of the universe consists of neutral events, which are the common ancestors of mind and matterâ (63). McHenry notes that Russell himself admits to owing much to Whitehead, his teacher and collaborator. The comparison of Whiteheadâs process ontology and Russellâs neutral monism is helpful especially since the contrast makes the former, less-well-known theory more clear. The same can be said of the subsequent comparison of Whitehead with Quine, who was also a student of Whiteheadâs. According to McHenry,â
âWhile Quine found much with which to agree in Whiteheadâs four-dimensionalism, he could not accept the idea that properties are legitimate parts of the ontology of science. Whiteheadâs ontology is dualistic, containing events and properties (which he called âobjectsâ). Quineâs ontology is also dualistic, containing events (which he also calls âphysical objectsâ) and classes (66).â
âBy providing detailed and clear comparisons of the event ontologies of Whitehead, Russell, and Quine, this chapter alone may make this volume worth the purchase, especially for analytic philosophers who have wanted to learn more about Whiteheadâs process metaphysics but have so far been intimidated by the prospect of confronting his Process and Reality.â
âThe fifth chapter explores connections between Whiteheadâs metaphysics and contemporary cosmology by examining his theory of extension. McHenry notes that although Whitehead knew nothing of Big Bang theory or post-Hubble cosmology, âin a rather uncanny manner his theory of cosmic epochs anticipates what has become the most challenging development in contemporary cosmological theory, namely the multiverse hypothesisâ (74-75). Again it is not possible for this reviewer to judge the accuracy of the treatment from the standpoint of physical cosmology. However, from the standpoint of metaphysics I find McHenryâs analysis to be in equal measures clear and insightful. He recognizes that âWhiteheadâs theory of cosmic epochs might very well appear quaint to the physicist steeped in contemporary string theory or inflationary cosmologyâ (85). However, McHenry argues convincingly that the value of Whiteheadâs project is not that it gets all of the details of physics right, but that the general metaphysical architecture that he erects helps one imagine a coherent multiverse theory.â
âMoving beyond the multiverse hypothesis, the penultimate chapter takes up the problem of time and the need for a unified theory for this present universe as its focus. McHenry contends that eliminating substances in favor of events is a critical first step toward developing a unification of general relativity and quantum mechanics. In particular, he defends âa version of C. D. Broadâs growing block universe consistent with Whiteheadâs late metaphysics and relativistic quantum field theoryâ (87). Rejecting the orthodox instrumentalism of the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, according to which everything proceeds deterministically until a measurement is made, McHenry recognizes that the probabilistic character of the quantum world must be brought together with a genuine realism (90).â
âMcHenryâs final chapter looks beyond physics to the broader philosophical implications of adopting an event ontology, specifically: the mind-body problem; perception and causation; personal identity; and free will. Readers interested in these topics will find helpful, if not exhaustive discussions of the implications of an event ontology for these perennial philosophical problems.â
âSteven Weinberg, Stephen Hawking, Neil deGrasse Tyson and others would do well to take to heart McHenryâs claim that âPhysics without speculation is sterile. Some metaphysical daring is required to break the spell of custom and conjure fresh perspectives â ones that will need to be formulated specifically and result in the possibility of testing to be taken seriouslyâ (86).â
âI can think of no better way to conclude this review than to quote from Quineâs own 1995 letter regarding McHenryâs proposal for the present project: âThe ambitious project which he now envisages is of precisely the sort that I like to picture as the next flowering of philosophy and science: a merging of rigorous, logically sophisticated methodology and ontology with the physicistsâ findings and quandaries in cosmology and quantum mechanicsâ (ix). There is ample reason to believe that this volume merits Quineâs praise.â
Navigation
Backlinks
There are no backlinks to this post.